5.1 Against the KK principle
(1i) M knows that if T is i+1 then ~(2i).
(2i) M knows that T is not i.
(3i) M knows that (2i).
(L) Luminosity
(KK) For any pertinent p, if M knows p then M
knows that M knows p.
[S] Simple
Creature Objection to (KK)
[I] Iterated
Pertinence Objection to (KK)
(C) If p
and all members of X are pertinent, p
is a logical consequence of X, M knows each member of X, then M knows p.
[GC] General
Closure: We know consequences of what we know.
[IC]
Intuitive Closure: Knowing p1,
…, pn, competently
deducing q, and thereby coming to
believe q is in general a way of
coming to know q. [Deduction is a way of extending knowledge.]
[N]
Nozickean Counterfactual Objection to (IC)
[P]
Probability Objection to (IC)
[V]
Vagueness Objection to (IC)
[R] Reflective Equilibrium
Defending Intuitive Closure
[IC] Intuitive Closure: Knowing p1, …, pn, competently deducing q, and thereby coming to believe q is in general a way of coming to know q. [Deduction is a way of
extending knowledge.]
[N]
Nozickean Counterfactual Objection to (IC) [cf.
Ch.7]
[P]
Probability Objection to (IC)
Ø No probability short of 1 turns true belief into knowledge. [cf. Ch.10]
Ø Reworking (C) to apply to single-premise inferences.
[V]
Vagueness Objection to (IC)
Ø Not vagueness in “know” but limits on M’s eyesight and M’s knowledge of
it.
Seductiveness of the KK principle
One cannot
knowingly identify a particular counterexample to KK in first-person present
tense. [K(Kp ∧ ~KKp) → KKp → ~K~KKp → ~K(Kp ∧ ~KKp)] [Ch.12]
Application: The “Glimpse” Paradox [Ch. 6]
(p) “The exam will be on the penultimate
day.”
(l) “The exam will on the last day.”
() “If the exam is on the penultimate
day, then the pupils do not know now that it will not be on the last day.”
5.2 KKk & KKω
One knows0 p iff p. One knowsk+1 p iff one knowsk that one knows p.
(k ∈ N)
(KKk) is false.
One knowsω
p iff one knowsk p for every k. (k
∈ N)
(KKω) is a logical truth [challenge
to the generalized argument against luminosity]
Ø Infinite many premises & attenuated luminosity [not a satisfying response]
Ø Knowingω may fail
the gradualness requirement.
5.4 [Belief about
the accuracy of one’s own estimates
needs margin for error.]
5.5 [Belief about
the accuracy of others’ estimates
needs margin for error.]
5.3 Reliability/Safety/Margin-of-Error
[O] Obtain; [SO]
Safely Obtain; [B] Believe; [K] Know; [FB] Falsely Believe;
[IPK] In a
Position to Know; [SfE] Safety from Error; [MoE] Margin of Error;
[c] a small positive real number; [u] any non-negative real number
(L) For all α, if Oα(C), then IPKα(O(C)).
[C is a luminous condition.]
(7) For all α and β, if v(α) = v(β), then Oα(C)
iff Oβ(C). [C’s obtainment
depends only on the value of the relevant parameter.]
(8) For all α and u, if |u – v(α)| < c, and Bα(O(C)), then for some β close to α, v(β) = u and Bβ(O(C)).
[One’s belief is not perfectly discriminating with respect to the underlying
parameter.]
(9) For all α and β, if β is close to α, and Kα(O(C)),
then ~FBβ(O(C)). [Connection
between knowledge and SfE]
(10) For all α, if IPKα(O(C)), then for
some β, v(α) = v(β) and Kβ(O(C)). [Def.
IPK: One is in a position to know
something determined by the value of a parameter only if one can know without
changing the value of the parameter.] [(9)
+ (10) → “SfE Assumption”: IPK only if SfE]
(11) For all α, if Kα(O(C)), then Bα(O(C)).
[Knowledge implies belief.]
(12) For all α and β, if |v(α) – v(β)| < c, then Oα(C) iff Oβ(C).
(13) For all u,
for some α, v(α) = u. [The
parameter varies continuously.]
(14) For all α and β, Oα(C) iff Oβ(C).
[Triviality: C obtains in all cases or
none.]
(15) For all α and β, if |v(α) – v(β)| < c, and IPKα(O(C)), then Oβ(C).
[MoE
Principle]
没有评论:
发表评论